The experimenter's view of the trees. |
For a therapeutic agent to improve outcomes in a given
disease, say sepsis, a fundamental and paramount precondition must be met: the agent/therapy must interfere with part of
the causal pathway to the outcome of interest. Even if this precondition is met, the agent
may not influence the outcome favorably for several reasons:
- Causal pathway redundancy: redundancy in causal pathways may mitigate the agent's effects on the downstream outcome of interest - blocking one intermediary fails because another pathway remains active
- Causal factor redundancy: the factor affected by the agent has both beneficial and untoward effects in different causal pathways - that is, the agent's toxic effects may outweigh/counteract its beneficial ones through different pathways
- Time dependency of the causal pathway: the agent interferes with a factor in the causal pathway that is time dependent and thus the timing of administration is crucial for expression of the agent's effects
- Multiplicity of agent effects: the agent has multiple effects on multiple pathways - e.g., HMG-CoA reductase inhibitors both lower LDL cholesterol and have anti-inflammatory effects. In this case, the agent may influence the outcome favorably, but it's a trick of nature - it's doing so via a different mechanism than the one you think it is.
Herein I will argue that enormous biological complexity severely
limits our understanding of the causal pathways of most diseases; that many
agents studied for the treatment of disease do not meet the causal pathway
precondition or are subject to the above limitations; that our hopeful quest to
discover treatments for disease leads us to markedly overestimate the
likelihood that any variable or pathway we discover and study is part of a
causal pathway to outcomes that are of clinical interest.
Consider the simple causal pathway in Figure 1.
FIGURE 1 |
Next consider Figure 2. S. pneumoniae triggers a causal cascade that leads to death, but it also triggers several other sequences that do not lead to death, represented as A, B, C and J, K, L. (These factors could be cytokines or any other immunological molecules.) Suppose that investigators researching clinical illness with S. pneumoniae discover these nine molecules and further research shows that, compared to levels of these molecules in patients without disease, levels in patients with clinical infection are elevated and positively correlated with the probability of death. Naturally we hope that the molecules we have discovered and can measure are part of the causal pathway to death from the illness, but we have no way of knowing based on these correlations. In this simple example, only a third of the molecules discovered and correlated with death are causal intermediaries. The other two-thirds are epiphenomena, and their manipulation by any means will not affect the causal pathway to the outcome of interest.
Much time, effort, money, and resources are devoted to discovery
and characterization of a given molecule in the study of disease. When one is discovered, it is the natural
hope of the investigator(s) that the molecule not only is critical for understanding
the biology of disease, but also that it will lead to a treatment for the
disease under study (or another disease).
But until the causal pathway is delineated, we have no way of knowing if
the molecule we are studying is a causal factor or an epiphenomenon, even if
its levels are strongly correlated with outcomes of interest. It is only after the development of an agent
that interferes with the molecule under study and its testing in a randomized
controlled trial in humans that we can determine whether that molecule is likely
to be part of the causal pathway in humans.
This problem represents a paradox: investigators learn that a molecule is
epiphenomenal only after they spend years characterizing it, developing a way
to modify it, and testing it as a treatment for disease in Phase I, II, and III
clinical trials. During that process, the
possibility that the molecule under study is simply a marker for disease is lost
in the hope that they are pursuing a treatment for disease. The possibility of finding only evidence of
an epiphenomenal role is the epitome of cognitive dissonance.
An important but currently unanswerable question is, what is
the ratio of [discovered] epiphenomena (markers for disease) to [discovered] causal intermediaries at any give point in history? How many branches similar to A, B, C, and J,
K, L in Figure 2 are present? How long
is the sequence represented by X, Y, Z? If we knew these answers, we would have a
better idea whether any molecule we discover that is correlated with outcomes
of interest is a causal one.
The fact that so many (all?) immunomodulatory therapies for
sepsis have failed suggests either that the ratio of epiphenomena to causal
factors is high, that redundant mechanisms and causal pathways are common or
highly time dependent, or a combination of these possibilities. Regardless of which may be the case, the
historical record of such therapies suggests that the probability of finding a
variable that is not epiphenomenal and is not subject to redundant pathways,
mechanisms, and/or insurmountable time dependence is very low indeed. The same problems likely bedevil the
investigation of variables and therapies in other diseases and disciplines.
This post, I'm afraid, will serve as little consolation to
investigators of therapies for sepsis and other recalcitrant diseases. But my purpose here is not to solace but to
try to understand the evidence and its limitations, and to use this
understanding to predict the results of future investigations and temper
expectations with reality. As far as
immunomodulatory therapy for sepsis is concerned, the evidence speaks for
itself: positive associations between known variables and outcomes of clinical
interest are either epiphenomena or are intransigent because of redundancy of
mechanisms, redundancy of causal pathways, or time dependency. Finally, "proof" of causation is subject to the limitations of multiplicity of effects of "independent" (controlled) variables. These problems with sepsis therapies provide
a case study for therapies in other diseases.
(See also: Why Sepsis Trials Fail by Roger Bone, JAMA, 1996; and an editorial by Opal and LaRosa in AJRCCM June 1, 2013.)
(See also: Why Sepsis Trials Fail by Roger Bone, JAMA, 1996; and an editorial by Opal and LaRosa in AJRCCM June 1, 2013.)
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.